Morality is objective

It might go without saying that a rational view of morality accepts that morality itself is a social tool, evolved particularly capably in humans. It’s not some randomly occurring spiritual process, neither is it a set of rules written by an imaginary man in the deep blue sky (or grey sky, if you live in Britain). This does not mean that rationality supports the idea of morality as relative, though. Whatever your ethical alignments, I hope to explain this simple issue with some simple words that should make you view morality in a slightly different way.

One doesn’t need to go into the ‘meta-ethics’ of the issue here, however the idea that morality is in some way objective is not alien to us. Very few think that heinous acts like murder, rape or torture can be justified except in extraordinary circumstances, and hence many agree that a great deal of acts are objectively wrong. Indeed, if we all agree that morality is civilly useful (ie, it stops us from killing each other arbitrarily, or for profit) then already we have a meta-ethical position that says, pragmatically speaking, morality should exist and should be objective so as to keep people from attacking us unfairly (because if morality is subjective, then it doesn’t work as people can ignore it and it fails to be a followed morality). There you go, you have a meta-ethical position – you’re already a better philosopher than most people I’ve ever debated with and we’re only two paragraphs in.*

However when it comes to morality as a whole, and putting our views about morality to the test, we can see that in our every day lives we act more like morality is actually relative. We don’t evaluate new moral ideas (such as those that try to outlaw deforestation, animal exploitation, or the tyranny of foreign dictators) from an objective, factual point of view. Instead, we mainly see such issues as a matter of personal or political choice, for which we can all decide individually upon.

Of course, this doesn’t make sense. Unless there is genuinely no evidence, or at least nothing significant (which is a rarity in morality) an act is still either wrong, else acceptable. In essence the point I’m making is that social acceptability doesn’t make something rationally justifiable, or rationally ignorable. This part is largely forgotten in society, as well as in the active sections of most moral movements.

We can point to animal rights as a perfect example. When the notion of ethical vegetarianism or veganism is bought up, it is often viewed as a matter of choice. But if the case is stated as ‘ethical’ then it isn’t just a personal choice, as we believe morality is objective (remember, we have a meta-ethical position!). Either the person who chose to ethically avoid animal products is acting unnecessarily, and is choosing it out of misplaced morality (and thus isn’t an ethical veggie/vegan at all), or else they are responding to a rational idea that animal exploitation is wrong. Only one of those two things is true because an act can’t both be right and wrong if we believe morality is objective. Fascinating – though not particularly complicated – stuff.

It isn’t just in wider society that the issue of relativism takes hold though, just look inside the moral movements themselves. Sticking with the animal rights movement, let’s take the issue of abolitionism. If you aren’t involved in the movement, or studying it, you will likely not know what abolitionism refers to. Briefly put, abolitionism is the position that criticises welfarists tactics, such as the promotion of ‘less cruel’ (supposedly less cruel, anyway) forms of animal use. Abolitionists claim to have reason based arguments, and legal/economic evidence of the problems with welfarism, and yet the majority of animal advocates remain under the impression that ‘all animal advocacy helps’ – including both welfarism and abolitionism under that banner. We can, after the analysis in the previous paragraph, respond by saying “Don’t be silly”. Whether or not we think animals deserve rights, it should be clear that they either do or they don’t. Similarly, whether or not we believe welfarism works, it either does or it doesn’t. Promoting the problems with ‘welfarism’ alongside the abolition of animal exploitation, and also not promoting the problems of welfarism and instead promoting less cruel forms of animal use are not two tactics that can rationally co-exist. If one is correct, the other is wrong. So “don’t be silly.”

As a final note on both of these points, of course it might be the case that the jury is still out on these issues, and that we don’t genuinely know as to which answer is right. Perhaps. But on this issue, like many others, the chances of us not really knowing are tiny. Animal rights isn’t a new area of study, Pythagoras had opinions about it and he’s been dead since about 495 BC. Slightly more recently (1989) Channel Four televised academic debates about it, and there is constant debate in the media about the cruelty of certain methods, or the legitimacy of others, etc. We currently kill in excess of 60 billion animals a year (this is a conservative estimate, as the sheer number of fish alone is probably around the trillion mark), one would think that by now someone would have some significant information on whether it was right or wrong. Similarly, on the nuanced topic of welfarism vs abolitionism, we’ve had welfarist tactics for at least 185 years. Is it likely we are still none the wiser as to whether or not it works? Possibly, but unlikely I would think. Even if the answer was just ‘there is no evidence that it is harmful’, then we would still have an answer.

Examples for good evidence, from top of the head common sense, or a quick google search? Most animal use is for food (there are no massive Bernard Matthews-style factory farms for vivisection, and comparatively few for clothing), Western health boards tend to say that well planned diets with no animal products are perfectly healthy, and furthermore excessive animal use might be causing environmental problems. These are all points that provide ethical evidence, whatever your initial opinions. Similarly, we’ve had animal welfare campaigns for 185+ years, in ever increasing amounts, and we exploit more animals today than ever before – with animal product companies actively volunteering to use ‘welfare’ labels such as ‘free range’ as a method of raising sales; labels for which they each extensively test as fairly as possible so as to examine the profitability in their own interests. Furthermore, the terms ‘cruelty’ and ‘compassion’ (which welfare campaigns are based around) are entirely subjective, and these campaigns themselves work within strict parameters which force any improvements to be incredibly minimal (of course they do, business does not offer profits away without a trade off). Again, these things are all evidence, and I find it strange that a rational analysis could lead to complete uncertainty by finding the exact same level of evidence, on every point, to be present on the other side of the discussion.

Still…it might…I suppose. We can’t do double blind experiments to analyse these things like in other forms of science, however, that doesn’t mean there isn’t evidence and an agreed set of basic morals in society (such as unnecessary suffering being wrong, sentient individuals being the subjects of morality, etc) with which we can expand and analyse in order to find consistent, rational results on new subjects. If nothing else I hope this article helps to persuade you of this, if you initially felt otherwise. So, the next time someone mentions a new moral or ethic that they have taken on board, judge it objectively. After all, so long as there isn’t a God looking down on us with an arbitrary check list of behavioural rules (and there certainly isn’t any evidence for us to believe that there is), then there is nothing subjective about morality.

*It’s a little more complicated than this, of course, but this isn’t the book itself, this is just a blog! In short I won’t go into it here as people don’t read book-length blogs.

Dear anti-science arguments, are you against science or society?

Science doesn’t hold many ‘values’. Unlike a religion, there are no facts that science is fundamentally attached to, or wobbly evidence that it throws faith behind – in the words of the founder of Skeptic magazine, Michael Shermer:

ʺScience is not the affirmation of a set of beliefs but a process of inquiry aimed at building a testable body of knowledge constantly open to rejection or confirmation. In science, knowledge is fluid and certainty fleeting. That is at the heart of its limitations. It is also its greatest strength.ʺ

As discussed in previous posts, then, science can only be said to hold one certain ‘assumption’, whereby it claims that when doing science, rationality is something we must follow. However, this could not be construed as a value. After all, science is the ultimate method of fact finding: if one can show evidence as to why a consensually agreed upon theory is incorrect, then science by it’s definition would accept it. If it’s not doing this, it isn’t science. Thus even the ‘value’ of rationality is up for discussion, if one can provide good reasons or evidence to start the discussion as to why.

I discussed in my last article why [permalink_to post=”Assumptions”]it doesn’t make a great deal of sense to challenge this ‘value’ at current, and why rationality is significantly different to any other assumptions that a ‘system of thought’ might hold[/permalink_to]. Rationality is both a necessary and a sufficient assumption for truth finding to maintain, and for facts to maintain. Thus the extent to which any criticism of science maintains an idea that science somehow has values, or an agenda, or is a tool for reinforcing traditional norms, is extremely worrying.

I’ll briefly discuss three examples of these criticisms to demonstrate the point.

Science has an agenda

You can find this criticism of science in a variety of places, but primarily from certain perspectives which tend to disagree with the mainstream. Feminism, Marxism, Anarchism, etc. The criticism goes that science is a tool for upholding harmful values as it helps to transmit or justify the norms of society.

Well, in a sense it is correct. Science is a method for finding truth, so if mainstream ideas are focused around a certain interest, then you would expect most current scientific method to be used in a way that somehow reflects that -although certainly not in a way which is in any way bias. For example, in a society where everyone, including even the most sceptical of people think that the world is flat, there are likely to be few scientific endeavours which are researching ideas relating to spherical objects orbiting the sun. This is a given – science won’t accept BS, but it’s still conducted by human beings with all of our vastly explored limits, and so science can’t know everything.

But how is this the fault of science? The criticism, whomever it is coming from, is really one of society. Science is still the best method of finding truth and when in the right hands, with the right raw data, it can do so. Science has no agenda; it’s people who have agendas. And to that end, science can be used for the ‘forces of evil’ just like talking, counting or walking can. You don’t hear people saying those activities have an agenda, though. The problem is with society, not with science. Hell, if you let science into more areas, (like I have argued we should, by making morality a pursuit of rational academia like other science) you may notice science is better able to identify when its perspective is incorrect. Known ‘science’ was pretty ignorant on the theories it had regarding a flat earth until scientific thinking was extended to disprove the idea that the earth was flat, so if you think the agenda of science is wrong, you should be justifying it by extending scientific thinking to show why. Blaming scientific method when the real problem is human agenda or limitation, is a mistake. It’s the input, not the method you disagree with.

Vivisection

Vivisection is another common criticism of science. My position on vivisection is clear cut as a matter of rationality. The social and biologically defined group that we belong to (sentient human beings) does not justify us to exploit or torture members of other biological or socially defined groups (sentient non-human beings) for the benefit of a fellow member of our preferred group. Sure we can argue self defence, or defence of our families and loved ones, and come up with interesting justifications for getting around this simple piece of reasoning. But vivisection goes beyond this. Vivisection asks us to calculate as positive the idea that we should be able to kill or torture, physically or mentally different sentient others, for the extremely slim chance of helping physically or mentally more similar others. This can’t really be justified, and until the day when vivisection is straight swapping a life for a life, (or somewhere near that equation) with no better alternatives for saving that life possible, then there isn’t much of a debate to be had as far as rationality is concerned.

Many people grasp this, or moreover perhaps don’t grasp this but ‘love animals’ and somehow get to the same belief on the immorality of vivisection…anyhow, those who do get this (for whatever reason) can often be found with a hatred of science for it’s perceived participation in the exploitation of animals. Note that, again, speaking, counting and walking also ‘participate in the exploitation of animals’ yet are deemed useful methods of acting. To repeat the previous criticism’s conclusion: it’s the input, not the method you disagree with.

And to conclude this criticism, in much the same way as the previous point once again, if you want science to be able to apply it’s own ‘value’ of rationality in such a way that it can not be usefully used to contribute to an agenda, then you need to allow science to be active in those areas where agendas are spoken about. In other words, if you believe science shouldn’t allow for vivisection, find a way to show how exactly morality should be objective in the same way science is.*

*This essay wasn’t intended to be a marketing exercise to sell my own theory of Rational Morality, but I see how it might look…

Climate Change

Climate change is a weird one. I’ve heard many a person say that science is pretty flawed as it can’t even agree on climate change. I’ve heard this been taken to the extent that a person claims science often opposes the truth about climate change. So let’s set one thing straight: scientific consensus backs the evidence on climate change. There are no half measures here, and even wikipedia agrees (and when wikipedia agrees with science on a controversial issue, you can be pretty sure that something obvious is going on!).

So, then, why the attack on science? Primarily because business, governments and various other interest groups have wheeled out the minority and presented them as ‘the other side of the argument’ in the same way that Christian groups wheel out the creationist “scientists” as the ‘other side of the argument’ about evolution. But make no mistake, the evidence on climate change is agreed upon as strongly as is evolution, if not more so.

So what’s the solution? Like with the past two examples, more science! Change our governments, businesses and the like to be bound by honest scientific method, and our media to respect it rather than staying bias toward this idea that truth is relative, which in turn amounts to nothing more than popularising and justifying attribution bias. The problem here is not with science, it is once again with people not being scientific enough.

So, to finish the article like a letter (the title is in letter format, so let’s keep up the pre-tense):

Yours sincerely,
Fellow advocate of science, and critic of society